This
post will focus on the sorts of psychobiological factors that created Wagner’s narrative construction of the Jews as
enemies of his cultural and revolutionary program. I am not going to
discuss his program or his anti-Semitism in general in this one; this
post is foundational for that. Instead, I am just going to focus on
brain science in general, and his paranoia and how that fueled his anti-Semitism, in specific. To some readers, you might consider this discussion
far afield, but I think in evaluating any person’s character,
particularly one who was thought to have mental problems as was the case with Wagner, you need some understanding of brain science. Plus, I
believe it is always good to pull back to a bigger and wider picture
so that biographical understanding isn’t unnecessarily constricted.
Those
who are up on neuroscience know that there is a wide amount of
compelling evidence that free will as normally understood doesn’t
exist. The neuroscientist Sam Harris, a
proponent of this theory, says, “Free
will is an illusion. Our wills are simply not of our own making.
Thoughts and intentions emerge from background causes of which we are
unaware and over which we exert no conscious control.” Sam makes
his case in this talk here.
In the talk, Sam details the moral issue by way of analogy. Dan Haggard summarizes it in this review: “When we get attacked by an alligator we tend not to get angry at the alligator, but instead we just try to run away. We don’t resent the animal because it’s just an alligator. However, if we are punched by a fellow human being we tend to resent that human. This difference in feeling Harris attributes to the notion of free will that guides us. We think that the animal can’t help do what it does, but we do think the person attacking us can. So, according to Harris, we resent things that we believe to have free will.”
In the talk, Sam details the moral issue by way of analogy. Dan Haggard summarizes it in this review: “When we get attacked by an alligator we tend not to get angry at the alligator, but instead we just try to run away. We don’t resent the animal because it’s just an alligator. However, if we are punched by a fellow human being we tend to resent that human. This difference in feeling Harris attributes to the notion of free will that guides us. We think that the animal can’t help do what it does, but we do think the person attacking us can. So, according to Harris, we resent things that we believe to have free will.”
Another
neuroscientist David Engleman, doesn’t completely rule out free
will, but in this podcast says:
The more we understand about human behavior, the more we understand how people's brains came to be the way they are from a very complicated intertwining of genetic and environment. It turns out if free will exists, it's really a bit player in what is going on in the brain. And the reason is your genes which you don’t choose, and your environment, including your in-utero environment and all your childhood experiences, we don’t choose that. These are the things that come together and make your brain the way it is and define a lot of your trajectory in life. And if you have free will, it can only modulate a lot of momentum and a particular direction.
If
you prefer reading, this article by the same author in The Atlantic covers the same
ground.
Why
this is relevant is that if we accept the proposition that there is no free will, it changes our
views of morality and culpability.
To
give a taste of the issue—I’m lazily stealing from Mark
Linsenmayer’s summary of a Eagleman’s views here—“Eagleman’s point here is that the criminal justice system
assumes a model of free will that is unsustainable given what we know
about neurology, and he gives examples like a normal guy with no
apparent deviant impulses suddenly starts exhibiting child molester
behavior. He’s subsequently diagnosed with a giant brain tumor,
which is then removed, and his behavior (and self-reported desires)
return to normal… but then they return, and what do you know? The
tumor’s back.”
But,
as Sam Harris argues, “A brain tumor is just a special case of
physical events giving rise to thoughts and actions. If we fully
understood the neurophysiology of any murderer’s brain, it would be
as exculpatory as finding a tumor in it” and, therefore, “the
whole conception of placing blame on him would erode.”1
The moral conclusion Harris—a well-know atheist—gives is that the “irony is if you want to be like Jesus and love your enemies, or at
least not hate them, one way into that is to view human behavior through
the lens of a wider scientific picture of causation.”2
There
are, obviously, people who are well versed in the science on which
the view rests, and disagree with this. David Dennett, a philosopher
and cognitive scientist, rebuts Sam here. But even he believes that the understanding of an absolute free will
in which we are morally culpable for our unfettered “free”
choices is incoherent. Dennett argues that we have “practical free
will” if not “theoretical free will” and are morally culpable
if we are “wired right”—that is free of retardation, brain
damage, or mental illness—but our choices are indeed greatly
limited by genetics, the environment and brain processes nonetheless.
So
even a free will supporter like Dennett believes that diminished
capacity greatly reduces or negates free will and such people are,
therefore, not culpable for what they do. The question becomes for
this blog, if you think free will exists as Dennett argues: did
Wagner have diminished capacity—that is, was he mentally ill? Many
people have argued just that—both in his time, and to this day. If
this is true, can he really be responsible for the bad in his
character and actions? Or, for that matter, the good in his works?
I
am actually going to take up the subject of his unique brain in more
detail at a later point, but I wanted to bring up one of his symptoms now: paranoia. You can consider this post as
the first in my exploration of his mental illnesses or, at least, his
mental uniqueness, as well as part of my on-going anti-Semitic posts.
I
have a theory, not proven as far as I know in the psychological
literature, but certainly true in my life-experience:
people with high IQs seem to be more susceptible to paranoia than
average folks. What IQ particularly tests is pattern recognition.
Therefore, my theory is that those who are able to see deeper, more
intricate patterns sometimes go amiss, and create rational and often
compelling theories that are, in fact, illusion or delusion. This guy has a similar theory, and has taken the time (unlike me who just
googled about a bit...) to find scientific literature to support this theory that paranoia has its roots in “a hyperactive pattern matching process, a reinforcement mechanism that rewards high-emotion conclusions, and a hyperactive state of arousal.” Wagner fits into this theory like a glove.
Now,
paranoia in schizophrenics is well-established in the literature, as
summarized here: “The
especially paranoid version of schizophrenia combines hyperactive
pattern recognition, specifically for patterns of conspiracy, with
other thought disorders, like bizarre ideation (literally bizarre
ideas) and ideas of reference (thinking that everything is personal –
people and events are referring specifically to them).” Paranoia, though, sometimes accompanies a wide variety of mental illnesses including depression, bipolar disorder, and obsessive-compulsive disorder.
I
have a good friend with schizophrenia—who has a high IQ and two
advanced degrees—and what I found is that she is always very rational and very good at narrative
construction. Because of this, she managed to convince virtually all of her doctors and friends—including me—of the truth of a particular delusional narrative in
spite of the fact that we knew about her disease. Only through a
process of fact-checking and communication between everyone were we
able to unravel that her narrative was based on paranoid “facts,”
and to free ourselves from our participation in her delusion.
Last
week's New York Times Magazine had a article called “A Theory of Conspiracy Theories.” The gist: “Perfectly
sane minds possess an incredible capacity for developing narratives,
and even some of the wildest conspiracy theories can be grounded in
rational thinking, which makes them that much more pernicious.”
Before
continuing, I do feel it is important to point out that
conspiracies do happen. All the time. The tendency to dismiss all
conspiracies as paranoia is as irrational as accepting all theories
as true. I believe that dismissing all conspiracy theories—as
many do out of hand—is wrong and dangerous. If someone
raises a serious question as to an event, it deserves a
serious answer. I appreciate the work of Skeptic magazine, for
example, to do just that (and they adequately debunked the 9/11 truthers
theory to me).
Back to the
article; it goes on to say that, “more recent scholarship by academics
like Mark
Fenster, Peter
Knight and
Robert Goldberg suggests that conspiracy theories do not come from a
particular personality type, I.Q. stratum or dispossessed fringe;
they erupt wherever unfathomable news collides with unshakable
beliefs.” But none of those cited are scientists, and I couldn’t
find any support one way or another in their works for relating IQ to
conspiracy theories. I don’t think the work has been done.
In
any case, even if conspiracy theories come from anyone on the IQ
range, my argument is that more compelling theories will come from
people with high IQs because of their more highly
developed skills in pattern-recognition and the ability to logically
detail the pattern that they perceive.
Whether
it is real or delusional can be incredibly hard to figure out.
To
wit, my friend David Lifton is a very smart guy, who wrote the NY Times bestseller Best Evidence
about the John Kennedy assassination. I do believe in this modern conspiracy
theory and I think that David has the best narrative about what
happened. He is an indefatigable researcher who has come up with a
huge body of persuasive evidence. But, I will add, David is exactly
the kind of high intellect, pattern-recognition guy who tends towards
paranoia. Therefore, I also recognize that his
narrative—consistent, fact-based, logical and compelling as it
is—may be utterly wrong. Just like my schizophrenic friend did, he
may have pulled me into his world of relentless, but ultimately,
delusional logic.
David Lifton no doubt pointing out the location of the head shot that killed Kennedy |
This
guy wrote a review in Amazon, which hits the nail
on the head:
They
say truth is stranger than fiction. People often ask whether David
Lifton is in touch with reality. Or is he intricately locked in a
nightmare from which he never awoke? For my part, this is a genuine
soul search. Lifton didn't gravitate in blind fury towards
conspiracy. He didn't suspect vast numbers of people of deliberately
hiding the truth. Whatever you think of his thesis, "Best
Evidence" is saturated in analysis and held together by
relentless logic. Suppose, if you will, that Oswald was the sole
killer of JFK. In that case Lifton is totally wrong and his book is
grotesque fiction. But it remains logical. His logic is just based on
a false premise (to use his own language). For me the question is:
are any of his crucial premises false? Lifton's conclusion is
fantastic. But consider the alternative. For Lifton to be wrong, all
the Parkland Hospital doctors and nurses, who originally attended
Kennedy, collectively misperceived or falsely described what they
saw. Or if they didn't, then all the Bethesda autopsy witnesses did.
Lifton doesn't pull this testimony out of thin air. It's on the
record. Lifton accounts for all of it in a way few other authors have
done. Most critics on the subject rely on discrediting witnesses,
usually on a large scale. The same problem applies to defenders of
the Warren Report. The point about David Lifton is that he doesn't
discredit. He explains. His explanation is outrageous, bizarre and
even absurd. Logic can be like that at times.
David
actually has much in common with Wagner, so I think he will return
later in the blog. Let me just say this: I do believe—because he
has proven it to me—his “outrageous, bizarre and even absurd”
narrative of the JFK assassination. If you are a fan of Carrie in
Homeland, I suggest David’s work to you. He has the same
intensity, focus and drive, though isn’t quite as manic as Carrie
was here:
The
green pen scene above looked nuts, but we learn that there was rational
reason for it, and she had developed her elaborate but true
narrative via color-coding. Got to love it.
Above is Nobel prize winning John Nash, subject of the film A Beautiful Mind. He saw both real and delusional patterns.
Then there is chess genius, Bobby Fisher, one of the great pattern-recognizers of all time. He later descended
into a state of paranoia, particularly against the Jews. (He was
Jewish). A psychological assessment is here.
Howard Hughes was another very successful and paranoid guy. Here is an article on his mental illness.
I could make a lot longer list, of course. Clearly in some humans, paranoia and high intelligence do go together. Each of these well-known folks were paranoid, but all had different types of mental problems. Nash had classic paranoid schizophrenia, Hughes was OCD, Fisher seemed to just have Paranoid Personality Disorder, Carrie is bipolar (yes, she is fictional, but paranoia can accompany that disease). The links between high intelligence and mental illness are not fully delineated, though there is a lot of research on the topic. For instance, see here and here. But most who study the area have concluded that they can be related. More later when I get to the direct topic of Wagner's mental state.
Now to Wagner and his paranoia. He was the type of guy who constantly created
elaborate narratives, sometimes dramatic and fictional, but often in
prose and, to his mind, grounded in history. His dramatic narratives
are often an ingenious reworking of his source material to construct
a compelling original narrative; he had a talent for this. His
prose, though, could be really out there, with flights of fancy in
which, for instance, he would write as if the mythical gods were
interacting directly with historical characters. An example given by
the the Wagner scholar, John Deathridge: “The essay the
Wibelungen...describes, among other things, a supposed relationship
between a historical figure, Friedrich Barbarossa, and a mythical
one, Siegfried.”3
As
for Wagner’s paranoia, Bryan Magee writes,
We have much evidence from people who knew him well that he was always inclined to think that something must be going on behind his back, that other people were up to something; and his friends took pains not to aggravate this. For instance, during the period when Nietzsche was close to Wagner he wrote a friend about some step he had decided not to take: “We both know that Wagner’s nature tends to make him suspicious, but I did not think that it would be a good thing to stir up his suspiciousness.4
All his biographers trace Wagner’s eruption of anti-Semitism to his time in
France when he groveled and near-starved in an unsuccessful
attempt to launch his operatic career. In Paris, he sought
assistance from the the most successful opera composer of his time, Giacomo Meyerbeer, who was Jewish. To Meyerbeer’s credit, he did help
Wagner in a number of small ways. The story of Wagner’s
relationship with Meyerbeer has been told well elsewhere, so I am
going to cut to the chase: he became paranoid about Meyerbeer and
concluded that he was scheming against him and, thus, Wagner wanted
to both publicly cut himself off from any association with him and get revenge for this, alleged, backbiting. Wagner's Judaism in Music was
written with this as his primary motivation, according to most
historians. For instance, Katz concludes: “Thus his attack on
Judaism appeared as the actual goal of the article and the unnamed
Meyerbeer only as an example. In reality, it was the reverse”5
Though
the the piece was published anonymously (in 1850), Wagner didn’t
otherwise hide his authorship and he was sure that Meyerbeer and
other prominent Jews in the music world knew he was the writer.
Wagner then became convinced that any bad press he ever received was
the result of Jewish machinations against him because of that
article. There is no evidence of this at all. When he republished
the essay under his own name in 1869, his reason for republication was to expose this
alleged conspiracy. Well, the result was that a segment of the Jewish
population did, finally, rise up to criticize him in an organized
fashion. After two decades, he finally had got the conspiracy he
long imagined!
There is no doubt Wagner truly thought
that there was a conspiracy, led by Jewish publishers, writers and
composers, against him. Nobody doubts he had this strong belief. But
there is no evidence it was true. I would argue that these
thoughts, strongly held but seemingly delusional, were beyond his
conscious control. It was this paranoia that was the launching-pad
of his anti-Semitism expression.
Do I conclude, given what I have said
about limitation on free will and his incapacitation by way of
paranoid delusions, that Wagner should be fully exonerated from
responsibility for any of his behaviors? No, as I have quite a few
puzzle pieces to add. But I do think what I have laid out in this
post, like the reality of the illiberal society I explored in this
post, should be taken into considerations in solving the conundrum of
Wagner.
End Notes
2 This quote comes at 53 minutes in.
3 Deathridge, Wagner Beyond Good and Evil, page 12, emphasis in original letter
4 Magee, The Tristan Chord, page 344.
5 Katz, The Darker Side of Genius, page 51. This book gives a full account of Meyerbeer and Wagner's relationship. Also, The Tristan Chord does as well in the Anti-Semitism chapter.
No comments:
Post a Comment